17

John Passmore in 1967 said that logical positivism

"...is dead, or as dead as a philosophical movement ever becomes."

Are there any modern philosophers that advocate logical positivism the same way Vienna Circle did? If not, to what principles and views should a philosopher subscribe to be a consistent logical positivist considering all criticisms and refutations?

5 Answers

4

Philip Kitcher's (1993) The Advancement of Science (Worldcat link) is the account of science I think of as closest to a contemporary version of Logical Empiricism/Positivism. Kitcher might deny that, and certainly his rhetoric in the book suggests he feels he's moved far away from that position. But when it comes down to it, some of us agree that he ends up pretty close to their views. He adds a sociological dimension to science (though that was not actually entirely lacking in the Vienna circle, either), but what he adds it to, and even the way he adds it, is pretty traditional LP.

One other place to look is in the HOPOS or "History of Philosophy of Science" movement. They now have a journal by that title. Among the philosophers working recently under that heading are a number of folks who are pretty sympathetic to classical LE/LP and they sometimes argue for the contemporary relevance of Vienna Circle positions and arguments. If you're interested in their early legacy in North America post-war you might also look at the Minnesota Studies volume "Logical Empiricism in North America" (contents/Worldcat).

4

You might be interested in the wikipedia article on Post-Positivist Verificationists. E.g.

After the fall of logical positivism, verificationism and empiricism more generally lost many adherents. This trend was stopped and in large part reversed in 1980 with the publication of van Fraassen's The Scientific Image. Constructive empiricism states that (1) scientific theories do not aim at truth, but at empirical adequacy; and (2) that their acceptance involves a belief only that they are empirically adequate.

4

Ernest Gellner was both a philosopher and a social anthropologist. He believed that positivism was the correct philosophy, but the logical positivists had expressed it badly. Rather than being an analysis of how all knowledge is obtained, Gellner thought that positivism should be seen as a quasi-ethical principle of how one ought to obtain knowledge. This position is interesting but a bit hard to grasp. A few quotes may help to explain it. The first is from the essay "Gellner's Positivism" by Ian Jarvie (in The Social Philosophy of Ernest Gellner, eds. John Hall and Ian Jarvie):

As Gellner construes philosophy, it [...] should, among other things, be partly empirical: the facts of the world make a philosophical difference. The overwhelming fact of the modern world makes a decisive philosophical difference. Furthermore, the particular philosophy of the facts so scorned by the Oxford disciples of the later Wittgenstein, namely positivism, seems to Gellner the correct philosophy -- even if it was seldom properly worked out by those who adhered to it (e.g. the logical positivists). This last qualification merely points to the fact that Gellner is a positivist yes, but something of a positivist sui generis because modern positivisms are 'trite and scholastic'. (p. 524)

Gellner elaborates his position on the theory of knowledge in his book Legitimation of Belief, in the essay "Positivism against Hegelianism" (in his book Relativism and the Social Sciences; Gellner memorably concludes this essay by saying: "the positivists are right. For Hegelian reasons." p. 67) and in an article entitled "An ethic of cognition" (in his book Spectacles and Predicaments). In "An ethic of cognition" Gellner writes:

The key idea in empiricism is the sovereignty of experience, and above all the exclusive and sole sovereignty of experience, in cognitive matters. What seems a trite truism (we learn by experience) becomes an unbelievably daring, radical, destructive, and difficult doctrine if reformulated more strongly so as to say -- we learn in no other way. (p. 169)

In particular, Gellner sees positivism as a method that excludes knowledge obtained through divine revelation, such as from a holy text. As Jarvie notes, "The positivism to which Gellner gives almost unqualified approval is d'Holbach's Le systéme de la nature" (Op. cit., p. 523). D'Holbach's 1770 book is sometimes called the "Bible of atheism" and is a classic Enlightenment account of a materialistic description of the universe. Small wonder that Gellner sometimes called himself an "Enlightenment fundamentalist."

Gellner sees positivism as the denial of the kind of world-views offered by religion, world-views in which the True, the Good and Beautiful converge within a cosmic story that dispels all doubt. These ideological world-views are not exclusively religious -- other all-encompassing belief systems that combine knowledge with morality are also excluded by positivism:

So, the sheer distribution of faith and disbelief itself confirms the truth of faith. Only those devoid of Grace doubt the existence of God; only neurotic resisters doubt the insights of depth psychology; only class enemies fail to see the cogency of scientific historical materialism [...] (p. 166)

Gellner defines positivism, or empiricism, as the rejection of these ideological worlds -- of religion, Marxist historical materialism, and so on:

What is empiricism, in general? The rough but correct definition, i.e., the one which brings out what really matters about the doctrine, is also highly paradoxical. It runs approximately as follows: empiricism is the a priori exclusion of a certain class of possible worlds, namely those worlds which satisfy some very deep general moral yearnings, roughly indicated above. (p. 168)

As Jarvie noted, Gellner believed that empirical facts about the modern world make a difference to epistemology. In particular, the most important fact of this kind is what he called "the Big Divide":

The biggest, most conspicuous single fact about the human world is the Big Divide between what may roughly be called the industrial-scientific societies and the Rest. The former possess, for good or ill, enormous manipulative and predictive powers over nature (though not over social processes), endowing them with the means both of mass destruction and of mass affluence and leisure. The latter miserably scrape a precarious living by agriculture or even cruder methods. Their techniques for either feeding or killing people are slow, inefficient, and labour-intensive. (p. 175)

Thus, positivism should be formulated so that it takes into account the Big Divide:

The importance of original, Comtian positivism was that it combined an articulation of the model with a historico-sociological awareness of the Big Divide. The trite and scholastic nature of many twentieth-century formulations of positivism are a consequence of an interest restricted to the model alone. The empiricist story of how an individual accumulates information about the world, is only useful if treated as an account of how some societies (but some only) have learned to investigate nature, and so as a parable of the Big Divide. (pp. 175f)

Gellner's position is that any attempt to prove the correctness of positivism as a theory of knowledge by means of a purely logical argument is doomed to fail. There is no way to prove, by logical argument alone, to someone who believes in an ideological world-view that he is wrong:

What is important is the fact that we have no logical or independent way of proving that such a 'circular' world, or strictly speaking a world sustained by reasoning which seems circular to an outside and hostile critic (or outside and hence hostile), cannot exist. On the contrary: it could well exist. A world so constructed as to make its most important features manifest to the good, and obscured from the wicked, might well exist. Perhaps, indeed, it does exist: and perhaps this world is just such a world. There is nothing in the very least logically self-contradictory in such a supposition. It cannot be excluded by logic. And it cannot be excluded by fact either, for it is constructed precisely in a way such that all facts can be accommodated. (p. 166)

Positivism should be seen as a quasi-ethical principle about how one ought to think and obtain knowledge, and as a rejection of all-encompassing world-views that combine the True and the Good. One more quote from Ernest Gellner's essay "An ethic of cognition":

Thus empiricism is normally presented as an account of how in fact we know (through experience), or sometimes as a metaphysic (the world is made up of experiences), such that, on either interpretation, certain worlds which defy or evade experience are, as a corollary or consequence of the initial position, excluded. On my account, all this is back-to-front. The essence or real starting point of the position is the exclusion of certain kinds of world, in an a priori manner. A certain possible misunderstanding should perhaps here be prevented: people may assume that describing a theory as quite an aprioristic one, is an attempt to denigrate it. This is in no way intended. Empiricism is an a priori doctrine; and it is also a good doctrine. (p. 171)

2

There are no modern philosophers who continue the tradition of the Vienna circle. But you're in luck, nearly all physicists continue it, even if they never heard of the Vienna circle. The philosophy started in physics, with Mach and Carnap (who was trained in physics), and it cannot die in physics, because it is essential for understanding physics, at least past 1900. Relativity, quantum mechanics, string theory, holography, that's all positivism.

This is why physicists ignore philosophers, and will continue to ignore them, until they get with the ball on this. There are no refutations of positivism, there cannot be, any physicist has grown so comfortable with this position, they can see it is self consistent.

What there was in philosophy was a horrified reaction: it resolved all the classical questions! Instantly. And not in a way that made previous philosophers look good, it showed the questions were meaningless! Of course philosophers buried it, it makes the classics in the field look dated and stupid. It was an academic political nightmare.

But it also has the advantage of being correct, and on the internet the position of academic politics is about as powerful as "First post!". So this can't be hidden. You can read the modern physics literature for modern positivism.

  • Based on a comment of yours, it seems that you do not understand how proofs of consistency must come from outside the system, if the system is susceptible to Gödel's second incompleteness theorem. You appear to have placed the verification axiom outside of science, by saying that "they don't expect to verify the verification principle". That very statement indicates that there are meaningful statements which do not need to pass the verification principle. Do you mean to say that there exists exactly one exempt statement?
    –  labreuer
    Dec 6, 2013 at 16:39
  • @labreuer: There are exactly as many exempt statements as are used to define what words mean. The verification principle is a definition of meaning, and as a definition it is exempt. Other definitions are also exempt, they are axioms that define terms precisely. It is never a problem in positivism, and it is only someone who doesn't understand the philosophy at all that can consider this a criticism (really). The idea that "verification can't be verified" is obvious to any positivist, it's not worrying, anymore than saying a "froobah" is a horse with three legs. Why? I just defined it!
    –  Ron Maimon
    Dec 12, 2013 at 1:41
  • I answered there, it's nothing to do with Godel. The objections are also kind of silly, the method to state positivism is as an equivalence relation between computational models of knowledge--- two systems that predict the same sense experience are equivalent. This doesn't require you to separate sense-experience and non-sense-experience, just to be able to tell when a prediction for sense-experience matches sense-experience, something you can program a computer with a camera and a microphone to do.
    –  Ron Maimon
    Dec 12, 2013 at 2:53
  • 2
    Is your answer to: "How do you know that you have established precisely what has meaning and what doesn't?", "I just do."? What I meant to get at, with Gödel, was how you know that your way of knowing is (i) consistent; (ii) complete. Incompleteness would happen, for example, if you've called some things 'meaningless' which aren't.
    –  labreuer
    Dec 12, 2013 at 6:01
  • Look, I gave you a definition, it is equivalent to Carnap's, it resolves the stupid objections to the idea, and it works for physics. There is no other competing idea out there, and if there were it would have to be positivistically equivalent. The way I know that the things I have assigned to the "meaningless" bin are meaningless is because that's what they are, by definition. It's a very important definition that is only established by looking at the physics examples I gave (although Mach predates them). Regarding "completeness", this is a formal property which is not relevant.
    –  Ron Maimon
    Dec 12, 2013 at 7:48
  • 1
    Why ought I accept your definition of what is 'meaningful', over and above a different one? You seem to not care about this. Are you perhaps making it out to be a basic belief?
    –  labreuer
    Dec 12, 2013 at 16:42
  • It's a basic belief, and there is no different definition of "meaningful". If you think there is, give it. Besides, it's not mine, it's Mach's, and it was shared by all the positivists.
    –  Ron Maimon
    Dec 14, 2013 at 20:06
  • I'm reticent to try and be the arbiter of what is is meaningful and what is not. Honestly, it seems like an exceedingly arrogant thing to do. I can talk about what is meaningful to me, but that's a function of my knowledge and my personality.
    –  labreuer
    Dec 15, 2013 at 3:29
  • @labreuer: The question of "what is meaningful" is solved in positivism, and it is not dependent on the person, and arrogant or not arrogant, Mach got it right. There is no competing definition, and it is essential for getting on in physics, where the question "what is meaningful" comes up all the time, especially since General Relativity and Quantum Mechanics.
    –  Ron Maimon
    Dec 18, 2013 at 14:22
  • labreuer's point about Gödel is slightly overlaboured, but the "positivist" physicist still needs to give a reasonable account for the truth of Mathematics. If it's in fact a logical positivism, then can the positivist sketch out a recovery of the logicist programme?
    –  Paul Ross
    May 19, 2015 at 10:07
  • @PaulRoss: Absolute truth in mathematics is the output of computer programs. You can verify these. The formal content of mathematics includes more, it includes conceptions of geometry and continua, and proofs that certain programs do not halt. The statement of the positivist program in mathematics would be to prove higher systems are consistent using no metaphysics, only computable ordinals, the ordinals described by Kleene's O (ordinal proof theory). The rest of mathematics is chosen for convenience of expression, and questions like the continuum hypothesis are non-questions a-la Carnap.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 19, 2015 at 22:39
  • 2
    This might be a better answer without the gratuitous and incorrect attacks on philosophy. If you want to argue that positivism started and continues within the discipline of physics, so be it, but the rest of what you wrote is just opinion-mongering.
    –  Chris Sunami
    May 21, 2015 at 14:16
  • There have been at many points as many Catholics who ignored philosophy until it could get on board. Where did that get us? This is just asserting your right to ignorance. Feel free, but don't pretend you care.
    –  user9166
    May 21, 2015 at 16:13
  • 4
    @jobermark: I agree with the Catholics in that dispute. Also, you're right, I genuinely DON'T care about philosophy: since the demise of positivism, it has been a completely worthless and fraudulent acedemic discipline, where people smoke marijuana and make friends with powerful people instead of actually contributing new knowledge. But I also am not pretending to care, I am just answering the question asked.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 22, 2015 at 1:00
  • By being present here, you are pretending to care. Respect the goal of the instiutions in which you take part, or leave them alone.
    –  user9166
    May 22, 2015 at 16:11
  • 1
    @jobermark: I should rephrase--- I care to destroy the fraud, but not to read or study it. There is no point in reading fraud, your only duty is to expose it. Then it's up to others to get on board.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 23, 2015 at 22:36
  • @RonMaimon unfortunately, you would need to prove there is a fraud, not that physicists would like to imagine there is one. Language and reality do not fit together as you pretend, and philosophers have basically proven that. Wish away Russel, pretend all of the demonstrations psychology makes that you see what you want whether it is there or not. Imagine we should have a world where the Catholics own science so that Galieo can be locked up, and we also owe you a reductivist playground.... Or make sense.... your choice.
    –  user9166
    May 23, 2015 at 22:54
  • 2
    @jobermark: I don't understand what you are saying, and I don't want anyone locked up. I am just exposing a problem: Carnap used a philosophy developed in physics to sort out nearly all the ancient problems of philosophy clearly and correctly. After a short period of acceptance, his ideas were buried, and his movement disappeared completely. There was nothing objectively wrong with the ideas, they were buried for purely political reasons, partly because the philosphers didn't understand them very well, and thought they saw contradictions, but mostly because they wanted their old problems back.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 26, 2015 at 14:12
  • @jobermark: I understand your comment now. Russell was a proto-positivist, there is nothing wrong with him at all, he is an honest person who was buried alongside Carnap, less successfully. The statement you made about Catholics was about philosophy, not science. The Catholics were lousy to scientists, but they were good to philosophers--- they required that philosophy hew to monotheistic ethics, so that the ethical systems that justified slavery could be permanently buried. When they lost ground, Nietzsche started justifying slavery again, and Heidegger joined a slave-driving genocidal order.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 26, 2015 at 14:17
  • Letting scientists, or the church or any other group not concerned with actual philosophy guide philosophy is aggressive overbearing elitist nonsense. You said outright that you "agree with the Catholics in that dispute" that means Galileo goes to jail. That is one instance of 'that dispute'. If you don't know what you mean, don't say it. This kind of outsider poking in and declaring all the residents idiots is too common here, restrain yourself and rely on arguments and proof, or go away.
    –  user9166
    May 26, 2015 at 14:17
  • @jobermark: I agree with the Catholics in (most of) their disputes over philosophy, not in their disputes over science. I don't want anyone to "guide" philosophy, I am not trying to "guide" anything--- I don't have or seek power. I am just explaining stuff, it's up to others to agree.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 26, 2015 at 14:18
  • Science was philosophy at that time.
    –  user9166
    May 26, 2015 at 14:18
  • @jobermark: No it wasn't. It just didn't have a name yet.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 26, 2015 at 14:18
  • And when they disagree for you to browbeat them, because you are certain you are right, and have no intention of listening.
    –  user9166
    May 26, 2015 at 14:19
  • That is sophistry. It was what people called it.
    –  user9166
    May 26, 2015 at 14:19
  • 5
    @jobermark: I have no power, no authority, so I can "browbeat" as much as I like, nobody has to listen to me, so it's not browbeating. The sophistry is ignoring the argument just because you don't like the tone. Just because people called science "natural philosophy" does not make it a branch of philosophy--- it operated by different rules of discourse right from the start, and it had objective experiments to sort out arguments, right from wrong. The philosophers didn't have an objective criterion for logic until Russell introduced formal logic and Carnap introduced Mach positivism.
    –  Ron Maimon
    May 26, 2015 at 14:20
  • 1
    Have you read about Kuhn or Feyerabend? I have read both Carnap and those, and they make more sense. Carnap was good at ignoring important details and making things seem resolved. Folks got on to the game and started ignoring him. The reason he cannot succeed is that theories combine the meanings of terms and the assertions about their effects in an irreducible package, the terms lose their meaning unless the theory is correct, but people pretend they are still clear.
    –  user9166
    May 26, 2015 at 14:25
0

Logical positivism has two sides, the side that presumes the observable universe can make sense of everything, and the side that insists nothing less precise than physics has any value.

The former is alive and kicking. For an approachable version of a hard-core reductivism that banishes the specialness of mind, you might try Daniel Dennett's "Consciousness, Explained". Most active philosophers accept some kind of reductivism as at least one aspect of the ultimate truth. Science has become compelling even for the very wooly-minded.

But the other side is just insulting hubris. We see very clearly, having looked at a wider swath of logics and grammars and faced down more complex aspects of science, that some things are meaningful without being clear, and are in no way improved by being reduced to finer terms. For instance, we cannot simplify the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics to absolute terms without just lying. And making it 'easier to understand' is accomplished by adding pointless extravagances like infinitely many parallel worlds. That is getting more vague, not more precise, just in a way that appeals to some intuition we share.

There is too much proof that even science needs to paw through muddled intuitions with important internal conflicts. We have wave-particle duality, we have group minds creating very convincing memories of nonexistent events, and highly crafted placebos (like hypnotism, acupuncture, and narrative therapies) that are stronger than real medicine, etc. They are not just going away because someone insists we not think about them.

Even if reduction is always possible, sometimes the right direction to go is not 'downward', or there is no clear definition of downward itself that is not clearly 'upward' at the same time. Emergentism and other forms of compromise imply that a less thoroughly grounded explanation is sometimes a better one, and positivism insists that will never be true, simply by defining the possibility away.

From an intuitionstic point of view, humans have evolved many sorts of conventions for making sense of the world, that are broadly shared, and it is only logical to use all of them, to the extent we can get those shared intuitions expressed in ways we can truly agree upon. Whether or not we could do with fewer is no longer a reasonable concern, once absolute reduction to a totally minimal set has failed. So given the weaknesses in the most basic approaches, like naive set theory, and first order arithmetic, we should look 'around' instead of 'down' for clarity.

Your Answer

  • Links
  • Images
  • Styling/Headers
  • Lists
  • Blockquotes
  • Preformatted
  • HTML
  • Tables
  • Advanced help

Not the answer you're looking for? Browse other questions tagged or ask your own question.